Conjunction elimination

Conjunction elimination
TypeRule of inference
FieldPropositional calculus
StatementIf the conjunction A {\displaystyle A} and B {\displaystyle B} is true, then A {\displaystyle A} is true, and B {\displaystyle B} is true.
Symbolic statement
  1. P Q P , P Q Q {\displaystyle {\frac {P\land Q}{\therefore P}},{\frac {P\land Q}{\therefore Q}}}
  2. ( P Q ) P , ( P Q ) Q {\displaystyle (P\land Q)\vdash P,(P\land Q)\vdash Q}
  3. ( P Q ) P , ( P Q ) Q {\displaystyle (P\land Q)\to P,(P\land Q)\to Q}
Transformation rules
Propositional calculus
Rules of inference
  • Implication introduction / elimination (modus ponens)
  • Biconditional introduction / elimination
  • Conjunction introduction / elimination
  • Disjunction introduction / elimination
  • Disjunctive / hypothetical syllogism
  • Constructive / destructive dilemma
  • Absorption / modus tollens / modus ponendo tollens
  • Negation introduction
Rules of replacement
  • Associativity
  • Commutativity
  • Distributivity
  • Double negation
  • De Morgan's laws
  • Transposition
  • Material implication
  • Exportation
  • Tautology
Predicate logic
Rules of inference
  • Universal generalization / instantiation
  • Existential generalization / instantiation

In propositional logic, conjunction elimination (also called and elimination, ∧ elimination,[1] or simplification)[2][3][4] is a valid immediate inference, argument form and rule of inference which makes the inference that, if the conjunction A and B is true, then A is true, and B is true. The rule makes it possible to shorten longer proofs by deriving one of the conjuncts of a conjunction on a line by itself.

An example in English:

It's raining and it's pouring.
Therefore it's raining.

The rule consists of two separate sub-rules, which can be expressed in formal language as:

P Q P {\displaystyle {\frac {P\land Q}{\therefore P}}}

and

P Q Q {\displaystyle {\frac {P\land Q}{\therefore Q}}}

The two sub-rules together mean that, whenever an instance of " P Q {\displaystyle P\land Q} " appears on a line of a proof, either " P {\displaystyle P} " or " Q {\displaystyle Q} " can be placed on a subsequent line by itself. The above example in English is an application of the first sub-rule.

Formal notation

The conjunction elimination sub-rules may be written in sequent notation:

( P Q ) P {\displaystyle (P\land Q)\vdash P}

and

( P Q ) Q {\displaystyle (P\land Q)\vdash Q}

where {\displaystyle \vdash } is a metalogical symbol meaning that P {\displaystyle P} is a syntactic consequence of P Q {\displaystyle P\land Q} and Q {\displaystyle Q} is also a syntactic consequence of P Q {\displaystyle P\land Q} in logical system;

and expressed as truth-functional tautologies or theorems of propositional logic:

( P Q ) P {\displaystyle (P\land Q)\to P}

and

( P Q ) Q {\displaystyle (P\land Q)\to Q}

where P {\displaystyle P} and Q {\displaystyle Q} are propositions expressed in some formal system.

References

  1. ^ David A. Duffy (1991). Principles of Automated Theorem Proving. New York: Wiley. Sect.3.1.2.1, p.46
  2. ^ Copi and Cohen[citation needed]
  3. ^ Moore and Parker[citation needed]
  4. ^ Hurley[citation needed]
  • v
  • t
  • e